Is ÒDo Unto
OthersÓ Written Into Our Genes ?
By NICHOLAS
WADE :
September 18, 2007
Source: http://www.nytimes.com/2007/09/18/science/18mora.html?pagewanted=2&_r=1
Many people will say it is morally acceptable to pull a switch
that diverts a train, killing just one person instead of the five on the other
track. But if asked to save the same five lives by throwing a person in the
trainÕs path, people will say the action is wrong. This may be evidence for an
ancient subconscious morality that deters causing direct physical harm to
someone else. An equally strong moral sanction has not yet evolved for harming
someone indirectly.
Where do moral rules come from? From reason, some philosophers
say. From God, say believers. Seldom considered is a source now being advocated
by some biologists, that of evolution. At first glance, natural selection and
the survival of the fittest may seem to reward only the most selfish values.
But for animals that live in groups, selfishness must be strictly curbed or
there will be no advantage to social living. Could the behaviors evolved by
social animals to make societies work be the foundation from which human
morality evolved?
In a series of recent articles and a book, ÒThe Happiness
Hypothesis,Ó Jonathan Haidt, a moral psychologist at the University of
Virginia, has been constructing a broad evolutionary view of morality that
traces its connections both to religion and to politics. Dr. Haidt (pronounced
height) began his research career by probing the emotion of disgust. Testing peopleÕs
reactions to situations like that of a hungry family that cooked and ate its
pet dog after it had become roadkill, he explored the phenomenon of moral
dumbfounding — when people feel strongly that something is wrong but
cannot explain why.
Dumbfounding led him to view morality as driven by two separate
mental systems, one ancient and one modern, though the mind is scarcely aware
of the difference. The ancient system, which he calls moral intuition, is based
on the emotion-laden moral behaviors that evolved before the development of
language. The modern system — he calls it moral judgment — came
after language, when people became able to articulate why something was right
or wrong. The emotional responses of moral intuition occur instantaneously
— they are primitive gut reactions that evolved to generate split-second
decisions and enhance survival in a dangerous world. Moral judgment, on the
other hand, comes later, as the conscious mind develops a plausible
rationalization for the decision already arrived at through moral intuition.
Moral dumbfounding, in Dr. HaidtÕs view, occurs when moral
judgment fails to come up with a convincing explanation for what moral
intuition has decided. So why has evolution equipped the brain with two moral
systems when just one might seem plenty?
ÒWe have a complex animal mind that only recently evolved language and
language-based reasoning,Ó Dr. Haidt said. ÒNo way was control of the organism
going to be handed over to this novel faculty.Ó
He likens the mindÕs subterranean moral machinery to an elephant,
and conscious moral reasoning to a small rider on the elephantÕs back.
Psychologists and philosophers have long taken a far too narrow view of
morality, he believes, because they have focused on the rider and largely ignored
the elephant. Dr. Haidt developed
a better sense of the elephant after visiting India at the suggestion of an
anthropologist, Richard Shweder. In Bhubaneswar, in the Indian state of Orissa,
Dr. Haidt saw that people recognized a much wider moral domain than the issues
of harm and justice that are central to Western morality. Indians were
concerned with integrating the community through rituals and committed to
concepts of religious purity as a way to restrain behavior. On his return from India, Dr. Haidt
combed the literature of anthropology and psychology for ideas about morality
throughout the world. He identified five components of morality that were
common to most cultures. Some concerned the protection of individuals, others
the ties that bind a group together. (See comment below on The Concept of Mind, by Gilbert Ryle,: for the Ghost in the
Machine ,)
Of the moral systems that protect individuals, one is concerned
with preventing harm to the person and the other with reciprocity and fairness.
Less familiar are the three systems that promote behaviors developed for
strengthening the group. These are loyalty to the in-group, respect for
authority and hierarchy, and a sense of purity or sanctity. The five moral systems, in Dr. HaidtÕs
view, are innate psychological mechanisms that predispose children to absorb
certain virtues. Because these virtues are learned, morality may vary widely
from culture to culture, while maintaining its central role of restraining
selfishness. In Western societies, the focus is on protecting individuals by
insisting that everyone be treated fairly. Creativity is high, but society is
less orderly. In many other societies, selfishness is suppressed Òthrough
practices, rituals and stories that help a person play a cooperative role in a
larger social entity,Ó Dr. Haidt said.
He is aware that many people — including Òthe politically
homogeneous discipline of psychologyÓ — equate morality with justice,
rights and the welfare of the individual, and dismiss everything else as mere
social convention. But many societies around the world do in fact behave as if
loyalty, respect for authority and sanctity are moral concepts, Dr. Haidt
notes, and this justifies taking a wider view of the moral domain.
The idea that morality and sacredness are intertwined, he said,
may now be out of fashion but has a venerable pedigree, tracing back to Emile
Durkheim, a founder of sociology.
Dr. Haidt believes that religion has played an important role in
human evolution by strengthening and extending the cohesion provided by the
moral systems. ÒIf we didnÕt have religious minds we would not have stepped
through the transition to groupishness,Ó he said. ÒWeÕd still be just small
bands roving around.Ó Religious behavior may be the result of natural selection,
in his view, shaped at a time when early human groups were competing with one
another. ÒThose who found ways to bind themselves together were more
successful,Ó he said. Dr. Haidt
came to recognize the importance of religion by a roundabout route. ÒI first
found divinity in disgust,Ó he writes in his book ÒThe Happiness Hypothesis.Ó
The emotion of disgust probably evolved when people became meat
eaters and had to learn which foods might be contaminated with bacteria, a
problem not presented by plant foods. Disgust was then extended to many other
categories, he argues, to people who were unclean, to unacceptable sexual
practices and to a wide class of bodily functions and behaviors that were seen
as separating humans from animals. ÒImagine visiting a town,Ó Dr. Haidt writes,
Òwhere people wear no clothes, never bathe, have sex Ôdoggie styleÕ in public,
and eat raw meat by biting off pieces directly from the carcass.Ó He sees the
disgust evoked by such a scene as allied to notions of physical and religious
purity. Purity is, in his view, a moral system that promotes the goals of
controlling selfish desires and acting in a religiously approved way. Notions
of disgust and purity are widespread outside Western cultures. ÒEducated
liberals are the only group to say, ÔI find that disgusting but that doesnÕt
make it wrong,Õ Ò Dr. Haidt said.
Working with a graduate student, Jesse Graham, Dr. Haidt has
detected a striking political dimension to morality. He and Mr. Graham asked
people to identify their position on a liberal-conservative spectrum and then
complete a questionnaire that assessed the importance attached to each of the
five moral systems. (The test, called the moral foundations questionnaire, can
be taken online, at www.YourMorals.org.)
They found that people who identified themselves as liberals
attached great weight to the two moral systems protective of individuals
— those of not harming others and of doing as you would be done by. But
liberals assigned much less importance to the three moral systems that protect
the group, those of loyalty, respect for authority and purity.
Conservatives placed value on all five moral systems but they
assigned less weight than liberals to the moralities protective of individuals.
Dr. Haidt believes that many political disagreements between liberals and
conservatives may reflect the different emphasis each places on the five moral
categories. Take attitudes to
contemporary art and music. Conservatives fear that subversive art will
undermine authority, violate the in-groupÕs traditions and offend canons of
purity and sanctity. Liberals, on the other hand, see contemporary art as
protecting equality by assailing the establishment, especially if the art is by
oppressed groups. Extreme
liberals, Dr. Haidt argues, attach almost no importance to the moral systems
that protect the group. Because conservatives do give some weight to individual
protections, they often have a better understanding of liberal views than
liberals do of conservative attitudes, in his view.
Dr. Haidt, who describes himself as a moderate liberal, says that
societies need people with both types of personality. ÒA liberal morality will
encourage much greater creativity but will weaken social structure and deplete
social capital,Ó he said. ÒI am really glad we have New York and San Francisco
— most of our creativity comes out of cities like these. But a nation
that was just New York and San Francisco could not survive very long.
Conservatives give more to charity and tend to be more supportive of essential
institutions like the military and law enforcement.Ó
Other psychologists have mixed views about Dr. HaidtÕs ideas.
Steven Pinker, a cognitive scientist at Harvard, said, ÒIÕm a big
fan of HaidtÕs work.Ó He added that the idea of including purity in the moral
domain could make psychological sense even if purity had no place in moral
reasoning.
But Frans B. M. de Waal, a primatologist at Emory University, said
he disagreed with Dr. HaidtÕs view that the task of morality is to suppress
selfishness. Many animals show empathy and altruistic tendencies but do not
have moral systems.
ÒFor me, the moral system is one that resolves the tension between
individual and group interests in a way that seems best for the most members of
the group, hence promotes a give and take,Ó Dr. de Waal said.
He said that he also disagreed with Dr. HaidtÕs alignment of
liberals with individual rights and conservatives with social
cohesiveness. ÒIt is obvious that
liberals emphasize the common good — safety laws for coal mines, health
care for all, support for the poor — that are not nearly as well
recognized by conservatives,Ó Dr. de Waal said.
That alignment also bothers John T. Jost, a political psychologist
at New York University. Dr. Jost said he admired Dr. Haidt as a Òvery
interesting and creative social psychologistÓ and found his work useful in
drawing attention to the strong moral element in political beliefs.
But the fact that liberals and conservatives agree on the first
two of Dr. HaidtÕs principles — do no harm and do unto others as you
would have them do unto you — means that those are good candidates to be
moral virtues. The fact that liberals and conservatives disagree on the other
three principles Òsuggests to me that they are not general moral virtues but
specific ideological commitments or values,Ó Dr. Jost said.In defense of his
views, Dr. Haidt said that moral claims could be valid even if not universally
acknowledged. ÒIt is at least possible,Ó he said, Òthat conservatives and
traditional societies have some moral or sociological insights that secular
liberals do not understand.Ó
=============================================
Gilbert RyleÕs The Concept of Mind
Source: http://www.angelfire.com/md2/timewarp/ryle.html
Gilbert Ryle (1900-76) was a philosopher at Oxford and who
made important contributions to the philosophy of mind and to "ordinary
language philosophy." His most important writings included Philosophical
Arguments (1945), The
Concept of Mind
(1949), Dilemmas
(1954), Plato's Progress (1966), and On Thinking (1979).
The Concept of Mind (1949) is a critique of the notion that the mind is
distinct from the body, and it is a rejection of the theory that mental states
are searable from physical states. According to Ryle, the classical theory of
mind, as represented by Cartesian ratioanlism, asserts that there is a basic
distinction between mind and matter. However, the classical theory makes a
basic "category-mistake," because it attempts to analyze the relation
betwen "mind" and "body" as if they were terms of the same
logical category. This confusion of logical categories may be seen in other
theories of the relation between mind and matter. For example, the idealist
theory of mind makes a basic category-mistake by attempting to reduce physical
reality to the same status as mental reality, while the materialist theory of
mind makes a basic category-mistake by attempting to reduce mental reality to
the same status as physical reality.
Ryle rejects DescartesÕ theory of the relation betwen mind
and body, on the grounds that it approaches the investigation of mental
processes as if they could be isolated from physical processes. In order to
demonstrate how this theory may be misleading, he explains that knowing how to
perform an act skillfully may not only be a matter of being able to reason practically
but may also be a matter of being able to put practical reasoning into action.
Practical actions may not necessarily be produced by highly theoretical
reasoning or by complex sequences of intellectual operations. The meaning of
actions may not be explained by making inferences about hidden mental
processes, but it may be explained by examining the rules that govern those
actions.
According to Ryle, mental processes are merely intelligent
acts.1 There are no mental processes that
are distinct from intelligent acts. The operations of the mind are not merely
represented by intelligent acts, they are the same as those intelligent acts.
Thus, acts of learning, remembering, imagining, knowing, or willing are not
merely clues to hidden mental processes or to complex sequences of intellectual
operations, they are the way in which those mental processes or intellectual
operations are defined. Logical propositions are not merely clues to modes of
reasoning, they are those modes of reasoning.
The rationalist theory that the will is a faculty within the
mind and that volitions are mental processes which the human body transforms
into physical acts is therefore a misconception. This theory mistakenly assumes
that mental acts are distinct from physical acts and that there is a mental
world which is distinct from the physical world. This theory of the
separability of mind and body is described by Ryle as "the dogma of the
ghost in the machine."2 He explains
that there is no hidden entity called "the mind" inside a mechanical
apparatus called "the body." The workings of the mind are not an
independent mechanism which governs the workings of the body. The workings of
the mind are not distinct from the actions of the body and may be better
conceptualized as a way of explaining the actions of the body.
Cartesian theory holds that mental acts determine physical
acts and that volitional acts of the body must be caused by volitional acts of
the mind. This theory is "the myth of the ghost in the machine."3
There is no contradiction between saying that an action is
governed by physical laws and saying that the same action is governed by
principles of reasoning. The motives of observable actions are not hidden
mental processes; they are propensities or dispositions that explain why these
behaviors occur. For example, the disposition to want or not to want something
is not explained by an intellectual act of wanting or not wanting that thing.
The disposition to want something is explained by the behaviors that are
involved in wanting that thing. Thus, the mind consists of various abilities or
dispositions that explain such behaviors as learning, rmembering, knowing,
feeling, or willing. However, personal abilities or dispositions are not the
same as mental processes or events. To refer to abilities or dispositions as if
they were mental occurrences is to make a basic kind of category-mistake.
The nature of a personÕs motives may be defined by the
actions and reactions of that person in various circumstances or situations.
The nature of a personÕs motives in a particular situation may not necessarily
be determined by any hidden mental processes or intellectual acts within that
person. Motives may be revealed or explained by a personÕs behavior in a
situation.
Ryle criticizes the theory that the mind is a place where
mental images are apprehended, perceived, or remembered. Sensations, thoughts,
and feelings do not belong to a mental world which is distinct from the
physical world. Knowledge, memory, imagination, and other abilities or
dispositions do not reside "within" the mind as if the mind were a
space in which these dispositions could be placed or located. Furthermore,
dispositions are not the same as behavioral actions, but actions may be
explained by dispositions.
Dispositions are neither visible nor hidden, because they
are not in the same logical category as behavioral actions. Dispositions are
not mental processes or intellectual acts, they are propensities which explain
various modes of behavior. Perceptions, thoughts, emotions, and feelings may be
understood as observable behaviors which hve various modes of production.
Ryle admits that his approach to the theory of mind is
behavioristic in being opposed to the theory that there are hidden mental
processes which are distinct from observable behaviors. His approach is based
on the view that actions such as thinking, remembering, feeling, and willing
are revealed by modes of behavior or by dispositions to modes of behavior. At
the same time, however, he criticizes both Cartesian theory and behaviorist
theory for being overly mechanistic. While Cartesian theory may insist that
hidden mental events produce the behavioral responses of the conscious
individual, behaviorism may insist that stimulus-response mechanisms produce
the behavioral responses of the conscious individual. Ryle concludes that both
Cartesian theory and behaviorist theory may be too rigid and mechanistic to
provide us with an adequate understanding of the concept of mind.
FOOTNOTES
1Gilbert
Ryle, The Concept of Mind (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1949), p. 297.
2Ibid., pp. 15-16.
3Ibid., pp. 15-16.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Ryle, Gilbert. The Concept of Mind. Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press, 1949.
Copyright© 2003 Alex Scott