Andrea Locatelli*  The Passion and the Interest  by Albert O. Hirschman Crossroads  ISSN 1825-7208  Vol. 6,  no. 1  pp. 96-101

* Catholic University of the Sacred Heart, Milan.  Copyright © 2006 by the author. Contact: andrea1.locatelli@unicatt.it

 

HirschmanÕs volume is admittedly a masterpiece. A number of reasons can  justify this statement: first of all, the main question informing the book is one  of those great conundrums that necessarily require a lengthy intellectual  journey. Secondly, the impressive analytical breadth makes The Passion and the  Interest a compulsory reading for political and social scientists, economists as  well as philosophers. Finally, HirschmanÕs thesis on the ÒideologicalÓ origins  of capitalism still remains one of the deepest arguments on the subject – as  insightful and penetrating as the Weberian or Marxist approach.  A theoretical puzzle paves the ground to HirschmanÕs argument: the rise  of capitalism is a function of the activity of merchants and bankers, whose  labour was originally considered sinful. So, what changed? How could a  morally shameful enterprise become ethically acceptable? The answer lies in  the moralizing role of the interest as opposed to the passions. From, say, Saint  Augustine to Montesquieu what occurred was a 180 degree turn. Just to  mention the former, at the beginning of the Christian era, he denounced three  basic sins of the fallen man – one of them being just lust for money and  possession. 

 

A change, but not a new ethos, emerged during the Reinassance period,  when philosophers like Machiavelli (and later Hobbes) insisted on taking man

Òas he really isÓ. The idea they pushed forward, quite disruptive for the time,  was that religious precepts could no longer be used to restrain the disorderly  passions of men. But still, their theory of the state did not take the interest into  consideration. Neither did other Seventeenth century philosophers, who rather  tried to use the principle of countervailing passions – that is play passions one  against the other in order to mitigate their effect. Even if here it is not possible  to discuss the point in depth, the reader would surely find HirschmanÕs  reading of Bacon, Spinoza, Hume and Hamilton fascinating.  Another step in this process came with the discovery of ÒinterestÓ and  ÒinterestsÓ as tamers of the passions. To be fair, the rehabilitation of the  concepts found his father in Machiavelli, but it was only in the Eighteenth  century, and mostly after HobbesÕ writings, that it came to the fore. The point  is a result of the previous step: while trying to pit passions one against the  other, those philosophers had to define which passions were to be tamed, and  which could be used as tamers. It is in this view that the interest gained value:  while the effects of interest-driven action are favourable, when men act out of  passion the state of affairs that prevails is disastrous.  Despite its lengthy and troublesome genesis, in the Eighteenth century  the concept of interest came to be acknowledged and accepted. Actually, its  definition remained quite loose and ad hoc, but this did not go to the detriment  of the concept. Most importantly, it proved able to display two assets –  predictability and constancy – whose effects played an important role both in

economic and political terms. While the passions made unpredictable and  irrational, the love for money-making could be cultivated by work and

commerce, both intrinsically innocent and mild activities – at least vis-à-vis the  wilderness of passions.  The remarkable conclusion is that the effects of such a conclusion worked  in the economic as well as in the political arena. As concerns the former, as  epitomized in Adam SmithÕs writing, the pursue of personal interest came to  be recognized as the key to prosperity. In political terms, after the Restoration,  there was much discussion about the advantages that might accrue to the  public interest from the presence of a variety of interests, and a certain tension  among them.  Obviously, the acceptance of interest did not come without opposition.  And, to be fair, HirschmanÕs account of critical voices is as accurate as the rest  of his work. But the point is that a new doctrine, not necessarily in conjunction  with a rising social class, came to the fore. As witnessed by the writings of  Montesquieu, Sir James Stuart and John Millar (all analysed in chapter 2), the  idea developed that the by-products of interest (i.e. commerce and industry)  would constrain authoritarian decision-making by the sovereign. Obviously,  as reflected in the modern liberal thought, the legacy of these thinkers is still of  utmost importance. Yet, as for liberalism, some critiques might be raised, and  actually have been, well before the expansion of capitalism all over the world.  It is therefore noteworthy that the author dedicated most part of the third  chapter to critical authors like Joseph Barnave, Adam Ferguson and Alexis de  Tocqueville.

That the book gained an instant and undisputed success soon after its  publication is a matter of fact. Also, by the light of the above-mentioned  hypothesis, it is no wonder why. Nonetheless, a few remarks might be useful

to better stress the conceptual innovations – and empirical consequences – of  The Passion and the Interest. Firstly, Hirschman provides a powerful genealogy  of commercial liberalism, proving that it has deeper (and more dignified) roots  than usually perceived. In fact, following his argument, the moral justification  of the interest is not just a post hoc defense of capitalism, but rather a cause of  its birth and development.  Secondly, the author goes a separate way from many liberal believers in  ruthless capitalism: so, while acknowledging the virtues of capitalism,  Hirschman also admits that some behaviors – even interest-driven behaviors –  might be dangerous, and therefore need to be contained. But here, and this is  probably one of the most controversial points, in his account he does not  address which activities (either political or economic in nature) are to be  tamed. And, most importantly, he does not say how to constrain dangerous  yet rational behaviors.  Finally, his argument gains new power within the context of  globalization. Albeit now the academic literature seems to have lost  momentum on the topic, the process once labeled as interdependence, then  globalization, is still under way. In this respect, Hirschman, although  implicitly, recognizes how self-interested economic behavior has consequences  that affect globalization too. Here again, if applied in the logic of the global  governance, his argument may be used as a good case in favor of a bottom-up

process of global institutionalization.  Obviously, some critiques may be raised (and indeed have been) against  this book. To be fair, most of them proved valid inasmuch as they stretch  HirschmanÕs analysis to account for the current developments of global  capitalism.

For example, those who point out the contextual (mainly  European) value of the ideas treated in the book find it easy to challenge their  explanatory power with reference to the expansion of capitalism. In a nutshell,  while the moral acceptance of the interest in the Western world may have  played a role in promoting trade and industry in Europe, this is hardly the  case in other continents, like Asia or Latin America. And, pushing the  argument a little farther, one may also note that even within European  countries a number of differences may be found: borrowing the famous  weberian hypothesis, the differences between Catholic and Protestant  Christianity may account for the different paths of capitalism in Northern and  Southern Europe.  Finally, given the role of ideas, an ontological issue may be raised: is the  change in ideas enough to explain changes in behavior? Hirschman starting  point is that capitalism, contrary to other revolutions, led a revolution without  a revolutionary class. Differently from the French revolutions, for instance,  there is no economic equivalent of a third estate supplanting an old aristocracy  during the capitalist revolution. As mentioned, this is why the author focuses  his attention on ideas as an independent variable. But, in the terms of the social  scientist, here lies the problem: how can we be sure that the relationship  between ideas and capitalism is not spurious? In other words, Hirschman does

 

" not take into consideration the possibility that other forces may be at work, or  at least that capitalism may be the result of an interplay between new ideas  and rising classes. To be fair, this is surely not enough to reject his conclusions,  but such a critique calls for a further investigation.  To conclude, why is The Passion and the Interest worth reading? The  answer may be found in the wise motto saying that you have to know where  you come from in order to know where you are going to. The trajectory of  liberal capitalism is still far from clear. Before its triumph is consumed,  whenever this is going to take place, it is wise to trace back its origins  following HirschmanÕs powerful reconstruction.